• Log In

The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast

A Philosophy Podcast and Philosophy Blog

Subscribe on Android Spotify Google Podcasts audible patreon
  • Home
  • Podcast
    • PEL Network Episodes
    • Publicly Available PEL Episodes
    • Paywalled and Ad-Free Episodes
    • PEL Episodes by Topic
    • Nightcap
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Pretty Much Pop
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • (sub)Text
    • Phi Fic Podcast
    • Combat & Classics
    • Constellary Tales
  • Blog
  • About
    • PEL FAQ
    • Meet PEL
    • About Pretty Much Pop
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • Meet Phi Fic
    • Listener Feedback
    • Links
  • Join
    • Become a Citizen
    • Join Our Mailing List
    • Log In
  • Donate
  • Store
    • Episodes
    • Swag
    • Everything Else
    • Cart
    • Checkout
    • My Account
  • Contact
  • Mailing List

Topic for #88: G.E.M. Anscombe on Ethical Judgment and Action

January 23, 2014 by Mark Linsenmayer 2 Comments

On Wed. 1/24 we spoke with Philosophy Bro about Elizabeth (aka G.E.M.) Anscombe. Go listen now to Bro's introduction to Anscombe.

Anscombe was a student of Wittgenstein's and is most famous for translating his Philosophical Investigations, and when Bro pitched this topic to me, he described her as the transition from Wittgenstein to Alasdair MacIntyre. This is puzzling, as Wittgenstein talks largely about language, whereas MacIntyre is all about virtue ethics.

In her essay "Modern Moral Philosophy" (1958) she claims that there's something wrong with modern ethics' use of "should." Of course, in ordinary language we run into many occasions where "should" is appropriate, as in "In chess, the bishops should only move diagonally" or "In chess, you should anticipate your opponents' moves." These kinds of "shoulds" are of course not considered part of morality, but Anscombe also says claims like "It's unjust to convict an innocent man" are also part of familiar, everyday parlance and do not require some kind of overarching philosophical ethics to be agreed upon. A plant needs water; people need love; if I borrow money from you, then I owe it back to you. All of these are likewise evaluative claims that she finds unproblematic. (And, to make the Wittgenstein connection, could be looked at as something like language games, though she doesn't use that term.)

Where modern ethics makes its mistake is then to pretend that these various bits of value can be summed up into a world of raw good and evil, where "should" is used not just in a given context as in the above but as an overall requirement on our behavior. She points to Aristotle's ethics as not making this mistake. For Aristotle, different organisms have their "good," their "virtues," but no obligation arises from these. Yes, since you're a person, you should be smart and just and prudent and eat foods that are good for you and get enough rest. But given those facts about human constitution, are you then obliged to do and be those things? Is there a moral law that requires you to do them?

Anscombe says that we only think in terms of moral laws and obligations because Christianity was dominant in our culture for so long.

It is as if the notion "criminal" were to remain when criminal law and criminal courts had been abolished and forgotten. A Hume discovering this situation might conclude that there was a special sentiment, expressed by "criminal," which alone gave the word its sense. So Hume discovered the situation which the notion "obligation" survived, and the notion "ought" was invested with that peculiar for having which it is said to be used in a "moral" sense, but in which the belief in divine law had long since been abandoned: for it was substantially given up among Protestants at the time of the Reformation. The situation, if I am right, was the interesting one of the survival of a concept outside the framework of thought that made it a really intelligible one.

Hume rightly discovered, she said, that supposed evaluative facts (e.g. that old chestnut of rationalist ethics: "It is fitting to respond to generosity with gratitude") don't actually motivate us to do anything just by us contemplating them. So he decided that morality must then be a type of sentiment. Anscombe says no: we have aims, we pursue activities, we have intentions, and all of that puts us in a position where we follow advice like that of Aristotle mentioned above, or the advice about playing chess, or running a just society. We don't have to associate these aims we have with "desires" in the sense of an inner impression as Hume thought, and again, these various evaluative bits do not and need not sum up to a special moral sentiment or anything like that. She likewise disses Hume's supposedly unbridgeable "is-ought gap"; she thinks evaluation is already built into these localized practices, and it is unilluminating to the point of distorting to try to tease apart the purely descriptive element and the normative element from our various terms, practices, and judgments.

Perhaps surprisingly, given the above, one of the sources of her objection to modern moral philosophy is her absolutist stance about certain prohibitions, such as killing the innocent. Shortly before writing this essay, she argued against Cambridge's award of an honorary degree to Harry Truman on the grounds that his atomic bombing at the end of WWII was unconscionable. He used the deaths of innocents as a means to acquire Japan's unconditional surrender, and this is right out for her. According to a utilitarian, Truman was justified if the good outweighed the harm, but for Anscombe, this means that all prohibitions are subject to compromise, which is a sign of utter corruption: you have no principles if this is the case.

She also wants to distinguish between cases like the above where killing innocents was vilely used as a means to an end and a case where, e.g. one's intent is to take out a munitions site (killing only soldiers), but there is a foreseeable risk that this will also result in the deaths of innocents. In such a case, you don't use those innocents as your means. This is the distinction between intended results (Truman intended to kill innocents) and merely foreseen but not intended results (bombing the munitions plant will kill innocents, but that was not the point of the plan).

She gives a clearer case of this "double effect": You're in a position where if you don't commit some ethical violation, you'll be put in prison, in which case your family will go hungry. A consequentialist might say "do the ethical violation if it wouldn't cause anything worse than you abandoning your family in that way; if you choose to abstain, you'll be responsible for them being left out in the cold." Anscombe thinks that we need to distinguish again between the intended (you are responsible for whether you do the unethical deed or not) and the merely foreseen (you are not responsible for this foreseen event that you do not intend).

How does this link up with her argument in "Modern Moral Philosophy"? Well, some people think that she's just trying to argue indirectly that we really should return to a divine command approach to morality. If you instead take her at her word, then this view of what you might call localized normativities (standards internal to a language game only, not generalizable into "the good" overall) can still be applied directly to these kinds of dilemmas. One has to decide how to act in a tough situation, and if you're a consequentialist, you just sum up all the good and bad anticipated consequences, choose the best (or least bad) option, and you've done the right thing. For Anscombe, I think, even if you do decide that circumstances necessitate that you commit some otherwise unjust act (I kill one innocent to save 1000), you might be understood and forgiven, but that still wouldn't make the act a just one in this circumstance: the local normative judgments stay accurate and don't get summed up into a command that you get praised if you obey.

You can download "Modern Moral Philosophy" here or purchase this collection of essays containing it.

We also read her essay "War and Murder" from 1961, an explicitly Catholic essay where she discusses legitimate state power, pacifism, and the double effect. Download it here.

Finally, we read sections sections 22-27 of her 1957 book Intention, which you can read online here or purchase

Intention is a remarkable work in itself, giving a systematic analysis of what an intention is (hint: it's not a feeling you have when you do something) and how to describe intentional actions (Do you describe Truman's action as "winning the war" or "killing innocents" or "bombing Hiroshima" or "giving an order to his generals" or what?). If you're a fan of Wittgenstein or want to see a really good example of analytic philosophy, I'd recommend that book over the two essays.

-Mark Linsenmayer

Facebooktwitterredditpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Filed Under: Uncategorized

Comments

  1. Rubi da Silva says

    January 6, 2017 at 8:00 am

    The link for the essay “Modern Moral Philosophy” is broken.

    This link worked for me. Came across it on Reddit. http://stevewatson.info/readings/philosophical_notes/Anscombe-mmp.pdf

    Reply
    • Seth Paskin says

      January 6, 2017 at 9:15 am

      Thanks Rubi
      I just tested the link in the article above and it worked for me.
      Seth

      Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

PEL Live Show 2023

Brothers K Live Show

Citizenship has its Benefits

Become a PEL Citizen
Become a PEL Citizen, and get access to all paywalled episodes, early and ad-free, including exclusive Part 2's for episodes starting September 2020; our after-show Nightcap, where the guys respond to listener email and chat more causally; a community of fellow learners, and more.

Rate and Review

Nightcap

Listen to Nightcap
On Nightcap, listen to the guys respond to listener email and chat more casually about their lives, the making of the show, current events and politics, and anything else that happens to come up.

Subscribe to Email Updates

Select list(s):

Check your inbox or spam folder to confirm your subscription.

Support PEL

Buy stuff through Amazon and send a few shekels our way at no extra cost to you.

Tweets by PartiallyExLife

Recent Comments

  • Mark Linsenmayer on Ep. 302: Erasmus Praises Foolishness (Part Two)
  • Mark Linsenmayer on Ep. 308: Moore’s Proof of Mind-Independent Reality (Part Two for Supporters)
  • Mark Linsenmayer on Ep. 201: Marcus Aurelius’s Stoicism with Ryan Holiday (Citizen Edition)
  • MartinK on Ep. 201: Marcus Aurelius’s Stoicism with Ryan Holiday (Citizen Edition)
  • Wayne Barr on Ep. 308: Moore’s Proof of Mind-Independent Reality (Part Two for Supporters)

About The Partially Examined Life

The Partially Examined Life is a philosophy podcast by some guys who were at one point set on doing philosophy for a living but then thought better of it. Each episode, we pick a text and chat about it with some balance between insight and flippancy. You don’t have to know any philosophy, or even to have read the text we’re talking about to (mostly) follow and (hopefully) enjoy the discussion

Become a PEL Citizen!

As a PEL Citizen, you’ll have access to a private social community of philosophers, thinkers, and other partial examiners where you can join or initiate discussion groups dedicated to particular readings, participate in lively forums, arrange online meet-ups for impromptu seminars, and more. PEL Citizens also have free access to podcast transcripts, guided readings, episode guides, PEL music, and other citizen-exclusive material. Click here to join.

Blog Post Categories

  • (sub)Text
  • Aftershow
  • Announcements
  • Audiobook
  • Book Excerpts
  • Citizen Content
  • Citizen Document
  • Citizen News
  • Close Reading
  • Combat and Classics
  • Constellary Tales
  • Exclude from Newsletter
  • Featured Ad-Free
  • Featured Article
  • General Announcements
  • Interview
  • Letter to the Editor
  • Misc. Philosophical Musings
  • Nakedly Examined Music Podcast
  • Nakedly Self-Examined Music
  • NEM Bonus
  • Not School Recording
  • Not School Report
  • Other (i.e. Lesser) Podcasts
  • PEL Music
  • PEL Nightcap
  • PEL's Notes
  • Personal Philosophies
  • Phi Fic Podcast
  • Philosophy vs. Improv
  • Podcast Episode (Citizen)
  • Podcast Episodes
  • Pretty Much Pop
  • Reviewage
  • Song Self-Exam
  • Supporter Exclusive
  • Things to Watch
  • Vintage Episode (Citizen)
  • Web Detritus

Follow:

Twitter | Facebook | Google+ | Apple Podcasts

Copyright © 2009 - 2023 · The Partially Examined Life, LLC. All rights reserved. Privacy Policy · Terms of Use · Copyright Policy

Copyright © 2023 · Magazine Pro Theme on Genesis Framework · WordPress · Log in