• Log In

The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast

A Philosophy Podcast and Philosophy Blog

Subscribe on Android Spotify Google Podcasts audible patreon
  • Home
  • Podcast
    • PEL Network Episodes
    • Publicly Available PEL Episodes
    • Paywalled and Ad-Free Episodes
    • PEL Episodes by Topic
    • Nightcap
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Pretty Much Pop
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • (sub)Text
    • Phi Fic Podcast
    • Combat & Classics
    • Constellary Tales
  • Blog
  • About
    • PEL FAQ
    • Meet PEL
    • About Pretty Much Pop
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • Meet Phi Fic
    • Listener Feedback
    • Links
  • Join
    • Become a Citizen
    • Join Our Mailing List
    • Log In
  • Donate
  • Store
    • Episodes
    • Swag
    • Everything Else
    • Cart
    • Checkout
    • My Account
  • Contact
  • Mailing List

Blaming Buried Prejudice: Neil Levy on implicit bias and moral responsibility

April 26, 2015 by Gil Percival 3 Comments

implicit-test-largeIf you haven’t seen it, there is a scene in Curb Your Enthusiasm when Larry David is casually walking across a parking lot having just parked his car. An African-American man walks past him in the same direction as Larry’s vehicle. Larry suddenly turns and clicks the button on his remote keyless system, locking his car doors with a swift electronic bleep that breaks the silence like a well-timed punch line. The man turns and glowers. “Think I’m gonna steal your car?” he challenges. “No . . . it’s not you”, Larry awkwardly bumbles, “it’s not a race thing”.

Whether Larry’s choice of moment to lock his vehicle was merely inopportune or whether he was really being racist is left to our imagination. What is interesting is the peculiar comic potential in this moment. If Larry’s locking his car door was a manifestation of a subconscious prejudice, then it’s almost as if we don’t know whether to protest or to laugh at him for his bad luck.

This inherent tension in our reactions brings up an interesting philosophical question – one that is taken up by philosopher Neil Levy in a couple of postings this month (here and here) on The Brains Blog. Science shows that though a person accused of discrimination may sincerely deny harboring any kind of prejudice, their choices and actions may have been modulated by ‘implicit biases’ operating below the level of their conscious intention. Are people morally responsible, and so legitimate objects of blame, for discrimination resulting from their implicit biases?

Levy argues that, on any plausible version of the most widely held forms of compatibilism about moral responsibility, we are not morally responsible for actions resulting from our implicit attitudes. In his blog post, he focuses on what he calls "control-based" theories. On control-based accounts, whether a person is morally responsible for some action is a matter of whether they possess the right kind of control over their performance of it.

Levy dedicates considerable space to articulating exactly what is the right kind of control, but the general conclusion is that this is what is crucially missing in the types of cases in question. When an employer chooses a worse qualified male candidate for a job role over a better qualified female candidate, due to implicit sexist attitudes biasing the selection process, she does not have the sort of control over her acting discriminatorily necessary for her to be responsible for it.

This is only the gist of a much more detailed and complex argument. Rather than wading into the fine details, I’ll just make some general remarks about Levy’s overall approach.

One thing that strikes me as interesting about the type of cases Levy is concerned with – cases where a person behaves discriminatively due to implicit biases - is that they are instances of what the philosophers Thomas Nagel and Bernard Williams referred to, in two classic papers from the 70s*, as "moral luck." Moral luck occurs when a person can legitimately be treated as the object of moral assessment despite the fact that what she is being assessed for is partly due to factors beyond her control. As Nagel points out, moral luck can enter into our moral assessments in a variety of different ways. Of particular relevance here is what Nagel calls "constitutive luck," or luck in the traits and dispositions that make us up, and "circumstantial luck," which is luck in the circumstances that we find ourselves in.

Take an example. Suppose a police officer fatally shoots someone in a situation that the officer perceived to be volatile and dangerous. At the time the officer sincerely believed her actions to be appropriate and proportionate to the threat posed. However, she is confronted with evidence that retrospectively forces her to realize that in fact she acted with disproportionate aggression. Her judgment of the situation was skewed by implicit biases about the victim’s race.

In certain respects, the officer’s actions were due to factors beyond her control. Her implicit biases are the product of conditioning by an environment that was, to a considerable extent, not of her choosing. Equally, that she found herself in a situation that made manifest those implicit attitudes in such a drastic way can also be attributed partly to factors beyond her control. Nonetheless, we would still expect someone in her position to feel a terrible form of regret over her actions.

In his paper on the topic, Williams talks about "agent-regret." Agent regret is different from what he calls "bystander regret," – the regret that someone with a spectator’s perspective might feel about some event - in that it is constituted by the subject’s first-person thought that it would have been much better had she chosen or acted otherwise. Agent-regret is also distinctive in the ways it is expressed. For example, it might include a desire to compensate a person for the harm they were done. Speaking of a lorry driver who, through no fault of his own, hits and kills a child, Williams writes, “we feel sorry for the driver, but that sentiment co-exists with, indeed presupposes, that there is something special about his relation to this happening, something which cannot merely be eliminated by the consideration that it was not his fault."

In a section of his later work, Shame and Necessity, where Williams is discussing Oedipus’s discovery, in Sophocles’ Oedipus Rex, that he has unwittingly killed his father and married his mother, Williams explains this special relation between the agent and the event thus – “in the story of one's life there is an authority exercised by what one has done, and not merely by what one has intentionally done."

Returning to the example of the officer, while we can acknowledge the tragedy of what happened, we would also expect her to experience profound agent-regret over what she did. Such an attitude cannot, and should not, be alleviated, cancelled out, or swept aside as irrational in light of the sorts of considerations adduced by Levy. Were the officer to merely feel a bystander’s regret because she was persuaded that she lacked the correct sort of control necessary to make her morally responsible for what happened, we would probably think that something was badly wrong.

One of the things that Williams thought to be especially important about examples of moral luck is that they show that there is something seriously out of sync between what he called the "peculiar institution" of modern morality and human moral psychology. That institution is founded on a related cluster of concepts – voluntariness, intention, control, blame and blameworthiness, amongst others – which it is the object of a great deal of contemporary moral philosophy to analyze and define. The consequence is that, for all its rigor and ingenuity, a great deal of contemporary moral philosophy does not really resonate with us on a personal and psychological level. It simply does not speak to the reality and particularity of our inner ethical lives.


*Bernard Williams's article "Moral Luck" and Thomas Nagel's response to it under the same name both appeared in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society in 1976. Williams's article was reprinted in the 1981 collection Moral Luck(available as a PDF here), and the Nagel article appears in the 1979 collection Mortal Questions. A video of a lecture summarizing Nagel's article is available here and here.

 

Gil Percival is the producer of UK philosophy/comedy podcast, The Philosofa. 

Facebooktwitterredditpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Filed Under: Reviewage Tagged With: agent regret, Bernard Williams, bystander regret, implicit bias, moral luck, Moral Responsibility, Neil Levy, philosophical blog, Thomas Nagel

Comments

  1. s. wallerstein says

    April 27, 2015 at 6:07 am

    What one is responsible for changes as society changes. In the 1950’s one would not have been responsible for choosing a less qualified male job candidate over a more qualified female one, but today one would be, because even if one has implicit biases on that subject today, one is responsible for being conscious of them and dealing with them, given that there is lots of information about them available to anyone with access to internet. In the 1950’s, as far I know, there was no research about implicit biases and thus, one was not responsible for becoming conscious of them and dealing with them.

    Reply
  2. Wayne Schroeder says

    April 28, 2015 at 10:29 am

    Good article implying the need to reformulate “modern morality” (I guess how it is now institutionalized, etc.) regarding issues of voluntariness, intention, control, blame, blameworthiness, etc., and develop a “human moral psychology” that better fits the “reality and particularity of our inner ethical lives.” Of course that leaves a lot undefined including what is moral, ethical and how it is related to the sliding scale of individual agency (free will) versus determinism (no freedom).

    Reply
  3. Keith Porter says

    November 25, 2018 at 5:22 am

    iIf the story of the police officer is set today, then she should at least know that such a thing as racist policing exists and represents a real social problem, that it is causing harm That makes her at least partially responsible for the harm done by her community, and makes her responsible for exploring whether her own attitudes or actions contribute to that harm, If she has not taken the trouble to examine her open implicit bias, then that is a decision she made, and for which she has responsibility. (In this comment, I’m parroting Larry May’s book on social existentialism, Sharing Responsibility. But only because it makes sense to me.)

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

PEL Live Show 2023

Brothers K Live Show

Citizenship has its Benefits

Become a PEL Citizen
Become a PEL Citizen, and get access to all paywalled episodes, early and ad-free, including exclusive Part 2's for episodes starting September 2020; our after-show Nightcap, where the guys respond to listener email and chat more causally; a community of fellow learners, and more.

Rate and Review

Nightcap

Listen to Nightcap
On Nightcap, listen to the guys respond to listener email and chat more casually about their lives, the making of the show, current events and politics, and anything else that happens to come up.

Subscribe to Email Updates

Select list(s):

Check your inbox or spam folder to confirm your subscription.

Support PEL

Buy stuff through Amazon and send a few shekels our way at no extra cost to you.

Tweets by PartiallyExLife

Recent Comments

  • Seth Paskin on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • John Heath on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • Randy Strader on Ep. 309: Wittgenstein On Certainty (Part Two)
  • Wes Alwan on PEL Nightcap February 2023
  • Kunal on Why Don’t We Like Idealism?

About The Partially Examined Life

The Partially Examined Life is a philosophy podcast by some guys who were at one point set on doing philosophy for a living but then thought better of it. Each episode, we pick a text and chat about it with some balance between insight and flippancy. You don’t have to know any philosophy, or even to have read the text we’re talking about to (mostly) follow and (hopefully) enjoy the discussion

Become a PEL Citizen!

As a PEL Citizen, you’ll have access to a private social community of philosophers, thinkers, and other partial examiners where you can join or initiate discussion groups dedicated to particular readings, participate in lively forums, arrange online meet-ups for impromptu seminars, and more. PEL Citizens also have free access to podcast transcripts, guided readings, episode guides, PEL music, and other citizen-exclusive material. Click here to join.

Blog Post Categories

  • (sub)Text
  • Aftershow
  • Announcements
  • Audiobook
  • Book Excerpts
  • Citizen Content
  • Citizen Document
  • Citizen News
  • Close Reading
  • Combat and Classics
  • Constellary Tales
  • Exclude from Newsletter
  • Featured Ad-Free
  • Featured Article
  • General Announcements
  • Interview
  • Letter to the Editor
  • Misc. Philosophical Musings
  • Nakedly Examined Music Podcast
  • Nakedly Self-Examined Music
  • NEM Bonus
  • Not School Recording
  • Not School Report
  • Other (i.e. Lesser) Podcasts
  • PEL Music
  • PEL Nightcap
  • PEL's Notes
  • Personal Philosophies
  • Phi Fic Podcast
  • Philosophy vs. Improv
  • Podcast Episode (Citizen)
  • Podcast Episodes
  • Pretty Much Pop
  • Reviewage
  • Song Self-Exam
  • Supporter Exclusive
  • Things to Watch
  • Vintage Episode (Citizen)
  • Web Detritus

Follow:

Twitter | Facebook | Google+ | Apple Podcasts

Copyright © 2009 - 2023 · The Partially Examined Life, LLC. All rights reserved. Privacy Policy · Terms of Use · Copyright Policy

Copyright © 2023 · Magazine Pro Theme on Genesis Framework · WordPress · Log in