• Log In

The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast

A Philosophy Podcast and Philosophy Blog

Subscribe on Android Spotify Google Podcasts audible patreon
  • Home
  • Podcast
    • PEL Network Episodes
    • Publicly Available PEL Episodes
    • Paywalled and Ad-Free Episodes
    • PEL Episodes by Topic
    • Nightcap
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Pretty Much Pop
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • (sub)Text
    • Phi Fic Podcast
    • Combat & Classics
    • Constellary Tales
  • Blog
  • About
    • PEL FAQ
    • Meet PEL
    • About Pretty Much Pop
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • Meet Phi Fic
    • Listener Feedback
    • Links
  • Join
    • Become a Citizen
    • Join Our Mailing List
    • Log In
  • Donate
  • Store
    • Episodes
    • Swag
    • Everything Else
    • Cart
    • Checkout
    • My Account
  • Contact
  • Mailing List

Epicurus’ Four Cures

May 20, 2015 by Hiram Crespo 19 Comments

epicurus

As the annals of history have it, in the sixth century Emperor Justinian had all the schools of philosophy that competed with Christianity finally closed. This was the last we heard of the Epicurean School, whose tradition had remained culturally vibrant for seven centuries. Epicurus had been among the first to propose the atom (2,300 years ago), the social contract as a foundation for the rule of law, and the possibility of an empirical process of pursuit of happiness: a science of happiness. These progressive schools were oases of tranquility, reason and pleasure known as Gardens, where the ideals of civilized friendship flourished and men, women, and even slaves engaged in philosophical discourse as equals.

If any set of doctrines can be considered the foundation of the Epicurean philosophy, it would be the Tetrapharmakon: The Four Remedies. For didactic purposes, the teachings were imparted in the form of short, easy to memorize adages. There are, to be fair, many more than four remedies in Epicureanism. However, these are known to be the core of the teaching out of which the rest of the philosophy flows:

Do not fear the gods.
Do not fear death.
What is pleasant is easy to attain.
What is painful is easy to endure.

In his Principal Doctrines 11-12, Epicurus argued for the study of science as a way to emancipate ourselves from irrational fears. For naturalists who don’t believe in gods or spirits, the first two negative statements may be translated as ‘Do not fear chance or blind luck, for it is pointless to battle that which we have no control over. It generates unnecessary suffering’.

Roman Epicurean poet Lucretius, in his De Rerum Natura, dedicates long portions of the philosophical poem to explaining how natural phenomena such as lightning and the movements of heavenly bodies are not the work of the gods and that fear of the gods is inconsistent with civilized life. Since he was unable in those days to produce a fully scientific theory to explain all these phenomena, he provided several possible theories for many of them without officially endorsing one, and humbly acknowledged that future thinkers would prove the main points of his naturalist and scientific cosmology, which they eventually did. And so we can say that his basic attitude was a sound one, and also that he respected our intelligence enough to not exhibit arrogance and certainty where he did not have conclusive theories. He allowed time to prove him right … and sincere.

That the prohibition against fearing the gods, and against fear-based religion in general, is the first and main taboo in Epicurean philosophy, remains refreshing to this day.

The second remedy is elaborated in a series of teachings and aphorisms which serve as a form of cognitive therapy to deal with the trauma of death. Among them, the most memorable is the purely hedonistic one. It is summed up thusly:

Death is nothing to us, since when we are, death has not come, and when death has come, we are not.

There is also the symmetry argument, which compares the time after our death to the time before our birth of which we have no memory. Since there is nothing there, why fear it? It is as unintelligent to be needlessly tormented about the afterlife as it is to be tormented about the state prior to birth. I frequently argue that it wasn’t just the teachings, but the manner in which they were imparted—within the context of a loving community of philosopher friends—that served as a consolation and that it is impossible to replicate the peace and conviction that Epicurus gave humanity without this sense of community.

The latter two positive statements in the Tetrapharmakon lead to Epicurean teachings on how we should evaluate our desires and discern which ones are unnecessary and which ones are necessary, which ones carry pain when satisfied or ignored and which ones don’t. By this analytic process, one learns to be content with the simple pleasures in life, those easiest to attain and which carry little to no pain. It is here that the real fruits of Epicurean insight begin to be reaped. The best things in life are free.

One of the first psychological tasks of every Epicurean is to become mindful of his or her desires and whatever pain or anxiety they may be generating. Another task is to learn to relish and appreciate the simple things when they’re in front of us. The good friends, the good foods and the refreshing beverages, the family, the good music, our proximity to nature, even our view of the sky which (as Carl Sagan advised us) should always humble us.

The good news, according to Epicurus, is that happiness is easily attained if we cultivate philosophy. He cites the need for thankfulness and for robust friendships as fundamental ingredients for the good life, and not only categorizes desires but also discerns between kinetic (active) pleasures that happen when we satisfy a desire, and katastemic (inert) pleasures that happen when we have no desires to satisfy, which he labeled as superior.

Harvard psychologist and happiness researcher Dan Gilbert confirms Epicurus’ insights, including how meaningful relations significantly increase the amount of pleasure and of memorable experiences that we gather throughout our lifetime. He uses different verbiage: natural happiness is that attained when we satisfy a desire (kinetic pleasure, in Epicurean parlance) whereas synthetic happiness is that which we enjoy regardless of attaining desires (katastemic pleasure).

Because synthetic happiness requires no externals, it is therefore superior, it is a sign of a liberated being. He argues the case for synthetic happiness by citing the example of the lottery winner and the paraplegic who exhibit similar levels of happiness one year after winning the lottery and losing the lower limbs, respectively.

This, in positive psychology, is being called the hedonic treadmill or hedonic adaptation: the habitual happy state that we always return to. Methods are being researched to increase the heights that are normal for each individual.

Gilbert’s theories, as far as I’m concerned, are Epicureanism by another name. One of the elements of Epicurean teaching that philosophers have struggled with the most throughout history is the idea of katastemic pleasure. It is often argued that lack of pain is not a definition of pleasure, but this is the art of happiness that Epicurus taught: that we must learn to be happy regardless of external factors and that it’s possible and desirable to cultivate katastemic pleasures via the philosophical disciplines. In fact, Epicurus argues that the very purpose of philosophy is to ensure an end to suffering and to create a beautiful, happy, pleasant life.

Gilbert’s research upholds katastemic pleasure as a necessary ingredient in human happiness and is beginning to reinvigorate the discourse on the philosophy of happiness that Epicurus had begun, and which was interrupted by Justinian 1,500 years ago. He also adds new concepts to our science of happiness and even proposes that we have a psychological immune system that fights unhappy moods.

Gilbert’s findings, along with research dealing with wellbeing in fields such as neuroscience and diet, point modern Epicureans in the direction of an interdisciplinary, practical reinvention of philosophy, which is just what we need if philosophy is to become once again the revolutionary, emancipatory cultural engine that it once was.

As to the Fourth Remedy, Epicurus reminded us of the temporal nature of bodily pain. We may get a fever, or a stomach ache, but within days our immune system fights it. In the case of more chronic pains, one gets used to them after some time. In nature, no condition lasts forever. The impermanence of all conditions is a consolation when we consider whatever pain they generate. A dismissive attitude towards pain takes discipline but it can be cultivated if we are mindful, disciplined, and develop a resolve to protect our minds.

Then there are mental pains and anxiety. These are systematically worked through via cognitive therapy. The resolution to follow Epicurus is a resolution to protect one’s mind. It’s impossible to be happy if we can’t control our anger and other strong emotions: we will go from one perturbed state to the next and never taste the stability of ataraxia, which translates as imperturbability and is the ultimate maturity that a philosopher can reach.

We live in a dysfunctional consumerist society filled with anxiety and neuroses, where few people analyse their lives, most have a short attention span and are usually uninterested in disciplining their minds and curbing mindless desires. If philosophy is understood as the Epicureans understand it, then it becomes evident that people desperately need philosophy today.

Many more things could be said about the consolations of Epicurean philosophy. I leave my readers with an invitation to study Epicurus and engage themselves and others in philosophical discourse. I promise that your life will be enriched.

Hiram Crespo is the founder of societyofepicurus.com and the author of Tending the Epicurean Garden (Humanist Press, 2014). This article originally appeared in Humanist Life.

Facebooktwitterredditpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Filed Under: PEL's Notes Tagged With: cures, death, epicurus, four, gods, happiness, hedonism, pleasure, therapy

Comments

  1. s. wallerstein says

    May 20, 2015 at 9:27 am

    Thanks. Your message or that of Epicurus arrived just the day when it was needed. Bless you.

    Reply
  2. Dandrea Dera says

    May 20, 2015 at 6:18 pm

    If only we could go back to Epicurus schooling, then we wouldn’t be restricted by puritan morals, and personal and sexual freedom and peace would be ours.

    Nonsense. There’s a reason why 700 years of that philosophy came to naught. Evolution of thought won, leave it behind.

    Reply
    • Kim Birley says

      November 17, 2015 at 4:42 am

      It did not come to naught, as any reader of Montaigne or Jefferson would know. One must not confuse being repressed with losing the argument!

      Reply
    • NELSON PEREZ says

      September 25, 2016 at 10:29 am

      It is not clear that it came to noth after 700 years. It is clear that it was persecuted and misunderstood as it is still today. It is clear that the sane eudamonistic pursuit of free agents was replaced by the afterlife promise, and philosophy did not, except Spinoza, Nietszche, affirm life.,

      Reply
  3. Mike says

    May 21, 2015 at 2:23 am

    “One of the first psychological tasks of every Epicurean is to become mindful of his or her desires and whatever pain or anxiety they may be generating.”

    “Because synthetic happiness requires no externals, it is therefore superior, it is a sign of a liberated being. ”

    “The impermanence of all conditions is a consolation when we consider whatever pain they generate. A dismissive attitude towards pain takes discipline but it can be cultivated if we are mindful, disciplined, and develop a resolve to protect our minds.”

    These are all statements a Buddhist would agree with. They sound spookily similar to Theravadan Buddhism. Could you explore the linkage more? Was Epicurus influenced by contemporary Indian philosophy?

    Reply
    • Alan Cook says

      May 21, 2015 at 9:10 am

      I think the question should be put in broader terms: Were there Buddhist influences on the whole Hellenistic philosophical culture of which Epicureanism was a part? Hiram called our attention to Justinian’s closing of the “pagan” schools of philosophy in 529 AD (although it’s very questionable whether this actually occurred in anything like the way the “annals of history” have recorded it.) For the record, the traditional “four schools” were: the Platonists, the Stoics, the Epicureans, and the Skeptics.

      For this discussion, the most important of these schools was the Stoics. While “stoic” and “epicurean” have very different connotations in contemporary English, and Stoic metaphysics was very different from the Epicureans’ atomism, there was a great deal of similarity in the ethical teachings of the two schools. For both, the highest good for human beings was a life characterized by ataraxia.

      I bring up the Stoics here because, while there’s been relatively little scholarly discussion of the Epicurean-Buddhist connection, there’s been a great deal of attention devoted to the relationship between Stoicism and Buddhism–primarily to the conceptual similarities, but also to the question of whether or not there might have been direct influence.

      To keep this comment from getting way too long, rather than go into these matters further myself, I’m going to leave you with a couple of links to starting points for further exploration:

      A historical investigation of the possibility of direct Indian influence on Pyrrho, the founder of Stoicism: http://www.josephwaligore.com/greek-philosophy/indian-influence-on-hellenistic-philosophy/

      A more general exploration of the similarities and differences between Stoicism, Epicureanism, and Buddhism:
      http://rationallyspeaking.blogspot.com/2013/02/buddhism-epicureanism-and-stoicism.html

      Reply
    • Hiram Crespo says

      May 21, 2015 at 10:13 am

      We can only speculate here. There’s no definite proof, but it’s quite likely because Epicurus lived in the Hellenistic Era after Alexander the Great, which opened up the Silk Road to China and India and the philosophers in Greece had begun talking about the “gymnosophists” (I think that’s the word they used), who were the yogis from India.

      I know Pyrrho, the father of the Skeptic School, had been to India, and many others with Alexander; and the Gandhara Buddhist culture emerged in the region that is now Afghanistan, which incorporated Greek aesthetics into Buddhism imagery, the only Greco-Buddhist culture in history.

      The key difference is that Buddha said that all suffering is dukkha (dissatisfaction), whereas Epicurus classified desires according to certain criteria (natural or unnatural, necessary or unnecessary), so Epicurus was not as ascetic and sought to develop a hedonic regimen based on these natural pleasures..

      By the way, one of the reviewers of my book was a secular Buddhist practitioner:
      http://secularbuddhism.org/2014/08/31/tend-your-garden/

      and in the chapter on the science of contemplation in my book, I draw heavily from Zen because of how closely it resonates with our epistemology, with the stress on direct perception of reality with our senses and faculties which Epicurus enshrined in the Canon and which forms the base of Zen. I think ancient Greeks called this “enargeia”, or immediacy of experience.

      Reply
  4. Jake Zielsdorf says

    May 27, 2015 at 2:09 pm

    News Flash: You can’t get off the hedonic treadmill, nor would anyone want to. It’s what makes life worth living.

    Reply
    • Alan Cook says

      May 27, 2015 at 7:28 pm

      So what have millions of Buddhist monastics, as well as millions of renunciants in other traditions, been trying to do for the past 2500 years?

      Reply
      • Kim Birley says

        November 17, 2015 at 4:40 am

        Note the word ‘trying’! We Epicureans would argue that they are missing the point.

        Reply
  5. Greatfon.com says

    April 3, 2020 at 5:22 pm

    It is this combination of factors that would, ultimately, allow people to experience happiness at the highest level. Although it may seem impossible to attain or sustain, there are people who follow epicurean beliefs and seek to experience this level of happiness in their lives.

    Reply
  6. APKun says

    April 22, 2020 at 4:43 am

    Epicurus wrote: Don’t fear god. Don’t worry about death. What is good is easy to get, and What is terrible is easy to endure.

    Reply

Trackbacks

  1. How #Religion is Bad for #Ataraxia | The Autarkist says:
    July 1, 2015 at 3:49 pm

    […] warned us against fear-based belief in general and fear of Gods in particular, and helped us to understand that gods do not intervene […]

    Reply
  2. Entering the Stoic World Pt.1- Cynicism 2.0 | Vibrant Bliss says:
    November 5, 2015 at 3:06 pm

    […] of philosophy, the Stoic Zeno (c.334-262), Plato (c.425-c.348), Aristotle (384-322), and Epicurus (341-270) in Greece, along with Chuang Tzu (370-278) in China, were all active within the space […]

    Reply
  3. Entering the Stoic World | The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast | A Philosophy Podcast and Blog says:
    November 6, 2015 at 9:21 pm

    […] of philosophy, the Stoic Zeno (c.334–262), Plato (c.425–c.348), Aristotle (384–322), and Epicurus (341-270) in Greece, along with Chuang Tzu (370–278) in China, were all active within the space […]

    Reply
  4. Self-Guided Study Curriculum | Society of Friends of Epicurus says:
    March 20, 2017 at 3:18 am

    […] Essay: Epicurus’ Four Cures  […]

    Reply
  5. Michel Onfray and the Counter-History of Philosophy | Society of Friends of Epicurus says:
    June 2, 2017 at 9:36 am

    […] Four Cures are a Philodeman invention, to which Onfray offers an alternative that includes what he calls a […]

    Reply
  6. Michel Onfray and the Counter-History of Philosophy – Epicurean Database says:
    June 5, 2017 at 8:33 am

    […] Four Cures are a Philodeman invention, to which Onfray offers an alternative that includes what he calls a […]

    Reply
  7. Happy Twentieth! – The Havamal, on Isolation | The Autarkist says:
    June 20, 2017 at 3:20 am

    […] Epicurean philosophy. We also have a new SoFE member, Nate, who came up with his own version of the Four Cures in the process of writing the essays that make up part of our membership request process. […]

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

PEL Live Show 2023

Brothers K Live Show

Citizenship has its Benefits

Become a PEL Citizen
Become a PEL Citizen, and get access to all paywalled episodes, early and ad-free, including exclusive Part 2's for episodes starting September 2020; our after-show Nightcap, where the guys respond to listener email and chat more causally; a community of fellow learners, and more.

Rate and Review

Nightcap

Listen to Nightcap
On Nightcap, listen to the guys respond to listener email and chat more casually about their lives, the making of the show, current events and politics, and anything else that happens to come up.

Subscribe to Email Updates

Select list(s):

Check your inbox or spam folder to confirm your subscription.

Support PEL

Buy stuff through Amazon and send a few shekels our way at no extra cost to you.

Tweets by PartiallyExLife

Recent Comments

  • Seth Paskin on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • John Heath on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • Randy Strader on Ep. 309: Wittgenstein On Certainty (Part Two)
  • Wes Alwan on PEL Nightcap February 2023
  • Kunal on Why Don’t We Like Idealism?

About The Partially Examined Life

The Partially Examined Life is a philosophy podcast by some guys who were at one point set on doing philosophy for a living but then thought better of it. Each episode, we pick a text and chat about it with some balance between insight and flippancy. You don’t have to know any philosophy, or even to have read the text we’re talking about to (mostly) follow and (hopefully) enjoy the discussion

Become a PEL Citizen!

As a PEL Citizen, you’ll have access to a private social community of philosophers, thinkers, and other partial examiners where you can join or initiate discussion groups dedicated to particular readings, participate in lively forums, arrange online meet-ups for impromptu seminars, and more. PEL Citizens also have free access to podcast transcripts, guided readings, episode guides, PEL music, and other citizen-exclusive material. Click here to join.

Blog Post Categories

  • (sub)Text
  • Aftershow
  • Announcements
  • Audiobook
  • Book Excerpts
  • Citizen Content
  • Citizen Document
  • Citizen News
  • Close Reading
  • Combat and Classics
  • Constellary Tales
  • Exclude from Newsletter
  • Featured Ad-Free
  • Featured Article
  • General Announcements
  • Interview
  • Letter to the Editor
  • Misc. Philosophical Musings
  • Nakedly Examined Music Podcast
  • Nakedly Self-Examined Music
  • NEM Bonus
  • Not School Recording
  • Not School Report
  • Other (i.e. Lesser) Podcasts
  • PEL Music
  • PEL Nightcap
  • PEL's Notes
  • Personal Philosophies
  • Phi Fic Podcast
  • Philosophy vs. Improv
  • Podcast Episode (Citizen)
  • Podcast Episodes
  • Pretty Much Pop
  • Reviewage
  • Song Self-Exam
  • Supporter Exclusive
  • Things to Watch
  • Vintage Episode (Citizen)
  • Web Detritus

Follow:

Twitter | Facebook | Google+ | Apple Podcasts

Copyright © 2009 - 2023 · The Partially Examined Life, LLC. All rights reserved. Privacy Policy · Terms of Use · Copyright Policy

Copyright © 2023 · Magazine Pro Theme on Genesis Framework · WordPress · Log in