• Log In

The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast

A Philosophy Podcast and Philosophy Blog

Subscribe on Android Spotify Google Podcasts audible patreon
  • Home
  • Podcast
    • PEL Network Episodes
    • Publicly Available PEL Episodes
    • Paywalled and Ad-Free Episodes
    • PEL Episodes by Topic
    • Nightcap
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Pretty Much Pop
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • (sub)Text
    • Phi Fic Podcast
    • Combat & Classics
    • Constellary Tales
  • Blog
  • About
    • PEL FAQ
    • Meet PEL
    • About Pretty Much Pop
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • Meet Phi Fic
    • Listener Feedback
    • Links
  • Join
    • Become a Citizen
    • Join Our Mailing List
    • Log In
  • Donate
  • Store
    • Episodes
    • Swag
    • Everything Else
    • Cart
    • Checkout
    • My Account
  • Contact
  • Mailing List

Diving with Melville

December 1, 2015 by Mark Anderson 8 Comments

MelvilleLThe author of a recent essay on Herman Melville’s first novel, Typee, labels the work a “hoax” and a “fraud” because Melville exaggerated or embellished various incidents of the story, which he based on actual events from his life at sea. The substance of the charge is very old news, dating back to the publication of the book. But what interests me is less the author’s timeworn complaints than his overwrought rhetoric. Why not employ a traditional, if less sensational, label? For, really, Typee is a standard work of “fiction grounded on fact,” or, better, “life spun into art.” Indeed, Melville based all but one of his works prior to Moby-Dick on his personal experiences. And even the exception, the wildly philosophical Mardi, is in a way a record of his personal intellectual experiences. The same is true of Moby-Dick, for Melville’s masterpiece may be read as an autobiographical account of his transformation from a philosophical “pondering man” into a free-spirited sage.

Moby-Dick is replete with references and allusions to Platonic philosophy, particularly to Plato’s Phaedo, which Melville had made a specific point of reading not long before beginning work on the novel. Like Moby-Dick, the Phaedo addresses many subjects at once, but as it is set in prison on the day that Socrates must drink his hemlock and die, it is foremost about the life and death of a philosopher. The opinions expressed in the work are extreme, and they revolve in particular around a total rejection of the living body: the body is the prison of the soul; the body and its desires are the cause of all evil; the body interferes with the pursuit of knowledge and virtue. For these and closely related reasons, the philosopher must purify himself by separating from the body as thoroughly as possible while alive, until death effects a literal and complete separation. The soul that has been properly purified by philosophy may even be liberated from the cycle of rebirth, in which case it will live forever after as a disembodied being among the gods. In his other works Plato consistently ranks the soul above the body, but in no other dialogue does he demean the body so entirely as he does in the Phaedo. Thus Ishmael warns all prudent ship-owners against enlisting any sailor “who offers to ship with the Phædon … in his head.” The problem, he says, is that a “sunken-eyed young Platonist” left alone at a “thought-engendering altitude” atop a mast-head will so withdraw from the corporeal world around him that he will spot no whales. The distracted Platonist may even, as Ishmael puts it later, fall into “Plato’s honey head, and sweetly” perish there.

This radical formulation of Platonism, which we may refer to as Phaedo-Platonism, exercised a powerful influence on the western philosophical and religious traditions. It comes out in the Neoplatonism of Plotinus, and of course in Christianity, too. Melville was nominally a Christian, but in his books as in his personal life he rarely let pass an opportunity to mock or criticize the faith. Typee was especially controversial for its rough handling of the Christian missionaries living and working among the Polynesian islanders. Moby-Dick carries on this tradition, and Melville even referred to the novel as a “wicked book” that he summoned with an “evil art.” In a letter to Hawthorne he identifies “the book’s motto (the secret one)” as “I do not baptize you in the name of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit, but in the name of the devil.” To two young admirers who visited him in 1859, Melville insisted that “What little there [is] of meaning in the religions of present day had come down from Plato,” but despite his admiration for Plato, he expressed nonetheless his disgust with “Christendom in general and in particular.” Such sentiments infuse and color Moby-Dick, often implicitly but sometimes explicitly through Ahab’s mad rantings. Therefore one scholar has described the novel as an expression of “inverted Platonism.” The phrase is apt, not least because Friedrich Nietzsche once characterized his own thought in precisely these terms, and Moby-Dick is a proto-Nietzschean novel.

Although I have just mentioned Ahab, “a grand, ungodly … man” (to quote one of the owners of the Pequod), his lust to kill the “grand god” Moby Dick is not the Nietzschean element I have in mind. Ahab does not affirm his own life, but according to Nietzsche, the affirmation of life is a necessary condition of the superior individual’s great health. So obsessed is the monomaniacal Captain with his hatred of the white whale that he would sacrifice his own miserable self to strike the beast dead. Therefore, not Ahab, but the narrator Ishmael is the authentically Nietzschean Yes-sayer of Moby-Dick. Ahab is vanquished by the God he hates, but Ishmael survives the catastrophe to become the man who narrates Ahab’s dark fate with such sparkling insight and wit. Ishmael by his own admission was suicidal when he went to sea, but when later he tells of his adventures there, he is overflowing with vigorous life. The fact that he is able to tell the story that is Moby-Dick demonstrates his profound familiarity with those questions that Dostoevsky refers to as “accursed,” but his manner of telling demonstrates more: namely, that although as a pondering man he meditates deeply on the accursed questions, he does not regard them as accursed, which is to say that he does not suffer from them. Ishmael has attained a state of Nietzschean joyful wisdom, that wisdom which acknowledges the world-historical horror of the death of God while simultaneously identifying the event, to quote Nietzsche, as “the meaning of our cheerfulness.” The Nietzschean-Ishmaelean free spirit understands that following the death of God “our ships may venture out again,” and “the sea, our sea, lies open again.” Ishmael understands this because Melville understood it himself, and he came to this awareness a full three decades before Nietzsche announced God’s demise.

Nietzsche once called himself “the first perfect nihilist of Europe” who had, he added, “lived through the whole of nihilism, to the end, leaving it behind, outside himself.” One element of Nietzsche’s meaning here has to do with what we may call “existential nihilism,” the agitated depression of “nihilism as a psychological state,” under the influence of which “the world looks valueless.” Nietzsche left this existential aspect of nihilism behind by learning not only to accept but to celebrate its metaphysical aspect, namely the death of God, which amounts in brief to the loss of faith in cosmic meaning or purpose and divinely decreed values and ends. Melville had more difficulty with this. During the period when he wrote Moby-Dick, he was at the peak of his mental and physical health, which, combined with his liberated intellect, enabled him to attain to a state of joyful wisdom. But the precipitous decline of his career, coupled with various personal and financial hardships, laid him low. For years after the public failure of his masterpiece Melville suffered from the accursed questions, and although he later settled into a grim sort of resigned tranquility, he never recovered his youthful Ishmaelean exuberance. If in the end he died a sage, there was no longer any joy in his wisdom.

Philosophical artists and artistic philosophers, however they diverge respecting doctrinal matters, often bond beneath the surface in striving to render an ideal image of the sage. Plato, Melville, and Nietzsche were like this, each of them expressing his conception of wisdom through the mask of creative philosophy. Nietzsche insisted that “Every profound spirit needs a mask: even more, around every profound spirit a mask is growing continually.” His own uncanny literary persona was his mask, as Socrates was Plato’s, and Ishmael Melville’s. Were Plato, Melville, and Nietzsche therefore perpetrating a hoax on the public? Not at all, or rather only on those readers committed to believing in superficialities alone. Perhaps as inhabitants of a hyper-ideological intellectual climate we ourselves have come to this point, but for the sake of our collective intellectual life, for the sake of philosophy and, more, for the sake of wisdom, joyful wisdom, let us hope not. Melville loved “men who dive,” and he was a “thought-diver” himself. Let us try to dive with him, swimming out beyond the shallows to explore the depths of life and thought. The exercise may be less than fashionable today, but it is endlessly rewarding.

Mark Anderson is Associate Professor and Chair of the Department of Philosophy at Belmont University in Nashville, TN. He is the author of Moby-Dick as Philosophy: Plato – Melville – Nietzsche; Pure: Modernity, Philosophy, and the One; The Thinker-Artist (Sophia and Philosophia); and Plato and Nietzsche: Their Philosophical Art.

Facebooktwitterredditpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Filed Under: Misc. Philosophical Musings Tagged With: Friedrich Nietzsche, Herman Melville, philosophy blog, Plato

Comments

  1. Wayne Schroeder says

    December 1, 2015 at 9:35 am

    Well done, enjoyable read.

    Reply
  2. Kevin P. says

    December 1, 2015 at 9:41 am

    This is a really interesting post, and I will have to pick up a copy of your book sometime soon (and maybe it will cause me to re-read Moby Dick, which I have been needing to do for a while).

    The fact that Melville and Nietzsche were concerned with similar ideas made me wonder about where Emerson fits in, and I was wondering if you talked much about Emerson in your book. I can’t quite remember what Melville thought of Emerson/how influenced he was by him, but I know there was some sort of relationship there. And Nietzsche was arguably influenced more by Emerson than any other thinker. Do you see Emerson as another model of the sort of “joyful wisdom” you talk about in your post?

    Reply
  3. Mark Anderson says

    December 1, 2015 at 9:58 am

    Thanks, Kevin. Yes, I do write about Emerson in the book. (Merton M. Sealts, by the way, has a good essay called “Melville and Emerson’s Rainbow.”) Melville’s remark, “I love all men who dive,” was inspired by his experience with Emerson (reading him and hearing him lecture once). Still, Melville had problems with Emerson similar to his problems with Plato, particularly the metaphysics and the optimism (though Plato is less obviously an optimist). Nietzsche was famously influenced by Emerson, but I wouldn’t call him his main influence. The Greek poets and tragedians, Plato, Schopenhauer, and many others were equally influential. In any case, there is much more on these matters in the book.

    Reply
    • Kevin P. says

      December 1, 2015 at 10:23 am

      Great. I’m excited to read it, and I will check out the Sealts essay too. My comment about Emerson’s influence on Nietzsche comes primarily from reading Jennifer Ratner-Rosenhagen’s book “American Nietzsche.” But whether Emerson had the most influence on his thought or was one among other equally influential thinkers matters less to me than just the point that Emerson was a strong source of inspiration. Anyway, thanks for your response and thanks again for a great post.

      Reply
  4. Anton says

    December 2, 2015 at 12:38 pm

    Re: “Therefore, not Ahab, but the narrator Ishmael is the authentically Nietzschean Yes-sayer of Moby-Dick.”

    A lot of people like Nietzsche generally, but are uncomfortable with his elitism. I’ve often wondered what Nietzschean philosopher without the elitism (a democratic Nietzsche?) would look like. Maybe Ishmael gives us an idea?

    But I’m not sure Ishmael can really be a Nietzschean without the elitism. At least based on my memory of the novel (which, to be fair, I haven’t read in years), Ishmael struck me as a rather ineffectual character; beyond his initial relationship with Queequeg, he mostly exists to tell the story, but is not so much of an actor in it. I suppose telling the tale is its own sort of action, but I would imagine a “democratic Nietzsche” to somehow be more of an actor in the world, not primarily a contemplater. E.g., when Nietzsche has anything good to say about liberalism, it’s usually about people like Napoleon, and I remember Nietzsche has a comment that liberals are good only when they’re fighting a war: “On closer inspection it is war that produces these effects [i.e., promoting a spirit of freedom], the war for liberal institutions, which, as a war, permits illiberal instincts to continue.” I’d imagine Ishmael would be much more detached and skeptical about that sort of “war,” yet it’s like Ishmael needs Ahab’s own “war” against Moby Dick (which is kinda sorta like a Jamesian “moral equivalent of war” or “war against nature”?) to find his own meaning as the contemplater and story teller.

    In any event, this is just a stream-of-consciousness comment based on vague memories of the novel, so take it as you will.

    Reply
  5. Mark Anderson says

    December 2, 2015 at 5:37 pm

    Hi Anton,

    I imagine that in the years between his sailing on the Pequod and telling his story Ishmael had several other adventures (like Melville himself, whose life at sea was wildly adventurous). But, more importantly, when I think of the philosopher with Nietzsche in mind–Plato too–I think less about the figures he wrote about–the overman, or, in Plato’s case, Socrates–than Nietzsche (or Plato) himself.

    Reply
    • Anton says

      December 3, 2015 at 1:11 am

      Fair enough… Here’s my comment reformulated to talk about the authors instead. You say (very insightfully), “During the period when [Melville] wrote Moby-Dick, he was at the peak of his mental and physical health, which, combined with his liberated intellect, enabled him to attain to a state of joyful wisdom.” I take it the phrase “joyful wisdom” here means something like what you meant when using the phrase “Nietzschean joyful wisdom” when you spoke about Ishmael. As far as I can tell, Melville was not an elitist at the time he wrote Moby Dick — he wrote about the working class crew very sympathetically, etc. If that’s a fair assessment, and it’s also true Melville attained a sort of “joyful wisdom,” then he somehow did so without the baggage of Nietzsche’s elitism. If so, I wonder how Melville did that (besides health and a liberated intellect), and I wonder if Ahab-like figures or institutions in his life were somehow necessary for that to happen, at least as a sort of countervailing force or counterpoint.

      Reply
  6. Mark Anderson says

    December 3, 2015 at 7:39 am

    Hello again Anton,

    You’re certainly right that Melville was no Nietzschean elitist (though there are traces of intellectual elitism in his letters, and the most famous passages in praise of democracy in MD may include intentional rhetorical excesses). But I believe he was his own Ahab. The mad Captain was an expression of certain elements of his own psyche. Consider that Melville himself, while away at sea for nearly four years, hunted whales; was held captive by, and escaped from, cannibals; participated in a mutiny; was imprisoned in, and escaped from, a seaside jail; wandered islands and slept on beaches; witnessed, to his horror, numerous brutal floggings aboard a US naval frigate; befriended poets, intellectuals, and savages; and more–consider this, coupled with the fact of his being by nature a “pondering man,” with tendencies toward melancholia and pessimism, and I think you’ll agree that he had in the store of his own experience sufficient material to possess an Ahab persona within himself. His overcoming of this part of himself (the darkness of this part of himself), was his route to joyful wisdom.

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

PEL Live Show 2023

Brothers K Live Show

Citizenship has its Benefits

Become a PEL Citizen
Become a PEL Citizen, and get access to all paywalled episodes, early and ad-free, including exclusive Part 2's for episodes starting September 2020; our after-show Nightcap, where the guys respond to listener email and chat more causally; a community of fellow learners, and more.

Rate and Review

Nightcap

Listen to Nightcap
On Nightcap, listen to the guys respond to listener email and chat more casually about their lives, the making of the show, current events and politics, and anything else that happens to come up.

Subscribe to Email Updates

Select list(s):

Check your inbox or spam folder to confirm your subscription.

Support PEL

Buy stuff through Amazon and send a few shekels our way at no extra cost to you.

Tweets by PartiallyExLife

Recent Comments

  • Bibliophile on Pretty Much Pop #143: Pinocchio the Unfilmable (Yet Frequently Filmed)
  • Mark Linsenmayer on Ep. 302: Erasmus Praises Foolishness (Part Two)
  • Mark Linsenmayer on Ep. 308: Moore’s Proof of Mind-Independent Reality (Part Two for Supporters)
  • Mark Linsenmayer on Ep. 201: Marcus Aurelius’s Stoicism with Ryan Holiday (Citizen Edition)
  • MartinK on Ep. 201: Marcus Aurelius’s Stoicism with Ryan Holiday (Citizen Edition)

About The Partially Examined Life

The Partially Examined Life is a philosophy podcast by some guys who were at one point set on doing philosophy for a living but then thought better of it. Each episode, we pick a text and chat about it with some balance between insight and flippancy. You don’t have to know any philosophy, or even to have read the text we’re talking about to (mostly) follow and (hopefully) enjoy the discussion

Become a PEL Citizen!

As a PEL Citizen, you’ll have access to a private social community of philosophers, thinkers, and other partial examiners where you can join or initiate discussion groups dedicated to particular readings, participate in lively forums, arrange online meet-ups for impromptu seminars, and more. PEL Citizens also have free access to podcast transcripts, guided readings, episode guides, PEL music, and other citizen-exclusive material. Click here to join.

Blog Post Categories

  • (sub)Text
  • Aftershow
  • Announcements
  • Audiobook
  • Book Excerpts
  • Citizen Content
  • Citizen Document
  • Citizen News
  • Close Reading
  • Combat and Classics
  • Constellary Tales
  • Exclude from Newsletter
  • Featured Ad-Free
  • Featured Article
  • General Announcements
  • Interview
  • Letter to the Editor
  • Misc. Philosophical Musings
  • Nakedly Examined Music Podcast
  • Nakedly Self-Examined Music
  • NEM Bonus
  • Not School Recording
  • Not School Report
  • Other (i.e. Lesser) Podcasts
  • PEL Music
  • PEL Nightcap
  • PEL's Notes
  • Personal Philosophies
  • Phi Fic Podcast
  • Philosophy vs. Improv
  • Podcast Episode (Citizen)
  • Podcast Episodes
  • Pretty Much Pop
  • Reviewage
  • Song Self-Exam
  • Supporter Exclusive
  • Things to Watch
  • Vintage Episode (Citizen)
  • Web Detritus

Follow:

Twitter | Facebook | Google+ | Apple Podcasts

Copyright © 2009 - 2023 · The Partially Examined Life, LLC. All rights reserved. Privacy Policy · Terms of Use · Copyright Policy

Copyright © 2023 · Magazine Pro Theme on Genesis Framework · WordPress · Log in