• Log In

The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast

A Philosophy Podcast and Philosophy Blog

Subscribe on Android Spotify Google Podcasts audible patreon
  • Home
  • Podcast
    • PEL Network Episodes
    • Publicly Available PEL Episodes
    • Paywalled and Ad-Free Episodes
    • PEL Episodes by Topic
    • Nightcap
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Pretty Much Pop
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • (sub)Text
    • Phi Fic Podcast
    • Combat & Classics
    • Constellary Tales
  • Blog
  • About
    • PEL FAQ
    • Meet PEL
    • About Pretty Much Pop
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • Meet Phi Fic
    • Listener Feedback
    • Links
  • Join
    • Become a Citizen
    • Join Our Mailing List
    • Log In
  • Donate
  • Store
    • Episodes
    • Swag
    • Everything Else
    • Cart
    • Checkout
    • My Account
  • Contact
  • Mailing List

Defer Your Dreams

January 4, 2017 by Alex Tzelnic 4 Comments

On an episode of Inside Amy Schumer last year there was a sketch called “Listen Alert.” The gist was that Listen Alert was an emergency service for people who feel the need to vent and aren’t receiving proper attention from their friends or significant others. Press the button on the Listen Alert necklace and vent away. But toward the end of the sketch one woman starts to describe a dream, and Schumer quickly interjects as a Listen Alert employee puts her hand over the woman’s mouth. “We will not listen to your dreams,” Schumer says. “We are not saints.”

There is something offensive about being subjected to someone else’s dream. Unless I am prominently involved, the vague description, senseless logic, and grasping, threadbare narrative are a form of verbal white noise—audible but strangely devoid of substance. And yet, for reasons that I can’t quite fathom, dream sequences continue to feature prominently in books, movies, and television.

Having your own dreams is a pretty cool feature of the sleeping brain, and potentially a crucial one. But no dream should ever be a crucial feature of a narrative. As Henry James famously advised, ”Tell a dream, lose a reader.” Many essays have explained why this is so from a literary perspective: dreams can be unreliable and confusing; dreams are a lazy way of conveying meaning; dreams often function solely as audacious displays of artistic flair. But I suspect there is a deeper issue with dream sequences—one that is rooted in how people process and understand experiences. I suspect that dream sequences are not just aesthetically off-putting but fundamentally so; that they are antithetical to the project of storytelling itself.

It is easy to see why understanding stories can be evolutionarily advantageous. An inability to accept stories would not only make one a horrible movie companion, but would be potentially debilitating. As Cody Delistraty points out in The Atlantic, in a piece on the psychological comforts of storytelling, “Stories can be a way for humans to feel that we have control over the world. They allow people to see patterns where there is chaos, meaning where there is randomness. Humans are inclined to see narratives where there are none because it can afford meaning to our lives—a form of existential problem-solving.”

In addition to helping us make sense of our world, stories also allow us to make sense of one another. A 2012 study by Dan Johnson, a researcher at Washington and Lee University, concluded that reading fiction increases empathy toward others. Other researchers have found that our brains are hardwired to understand stories. The cognitive scientist Veronique Boulenger has shown that both the language and the experiential parts of the brain light up when hearing a story, as if the events are actually happening to you. As Annie Murphy Paul concludes in an article for the New York Times that cites the above study, “Reading great literature, it has long been averred, enlarges and improves us as human beings. Brain science shows this claim is truer than we imagined.”

But it's hard to see how it could be similarly advantageous to better understand the dreams of others. The brain may light up when listening to a story, but listening to a dream is often described as “mind-numbing.” I don’t think this phenomenon has been studied, but I would speculate that the brain is not active in the same way when encountering someone else’s dream. Perhaps this is because we are all too aware when being subjected to a dream that it lacks the dramatic or instructive intention of a fully realized story. This doesn’t imply that dreams are meaningless, but that their power as a narrative form might be.

This premise becomes clearer when we consider the logical structure of stories. In The Art of Fiction, John Gardner writes, “The most important single notion in the theory of fiction I have outlined—essentially the traditional theory of our civilization’s literature—is that of the vivid and continuous fictional dream.” In order for one to believe a story, one must buy in: one must experience the narrative with the same lucidity one experiences a dream. Any deviations from the logical structure of a fictional world will only serve to undermine its reality. If I were to write a political thriller only to have it literally rain cats and dogs, this outlying feature would make it uncomfortably obvious to the reader that the story was but a story. However if my story were a work of magical realism, about a Labrador that has no friends until he does a rain dance and it suddenly starts raining cats and dogs, the logic of my world remains intact even if the events are illogical.

On the contrary, one’s own reality is experienced through direct sensory perception. Unless I’m on heavy drugs, or suffering a mental breakdown, I’m convinced that my experience is a reasonably accurate representation of the world around me. I experience, therefore I am. In fiction, or fictional worlds, one needs to be similarly convinced that the author is providing an accurate representation of the world they’ve created. There is an implicit understanding that the events being portrayed did not occur, but if the portrayal is done well enough, that understanding need not be acknowledged.

Thus, fiction is a suspension of disbelief. There was no friendless Labrador that actually caused cats and dogs to precipitate from the sky. The power of the story does not hinge on its veracity, it hinges on the dramatic impact created by the vivid and continuous fictional dream. This is where dream sequences fail us—they propagate chaos and randomness where we expect to see order. A fictional world is reality once removed—an acceptable fabrication reliant upon the perceived reliability of its author. A dream sequence, however, is something stranger: it requires a double suspension of disbelief—reality twice removed. A character experiencing a dream sequence is a fictional subject weaving a fictional story, a hallucination taking place within a mirage. There is no need for a character's dream to adhere to the logical structure of the fictional world the character inhabits. The falsity of the dream, rather than enhancing the fabrication, thereby exposes it, as the story becomes a teetering house of cards. As soon as the Labrador with no friends starts dreaming, the author is asking me to buy in twice, and the “vivid and continuous fictional dream” I’ve been immersed in is suddenly interrupted by the mental leap required to sustain the dream at a secondary narrative level. There is taxation without representation: I’m required to further inflate the fictional balloon without the balloon actually expanding.

Of course, there have been plenty of exceptions to the “Tell a dream, lose a reader” dictum; dream sequences that added to the enjoyment of a narrative and didn’t “awaken” the audience to its status as fiction (the Dude’s galactic bowling trip in The Big Lebowski comes to mind). But I would posit that these sequences were successful in and of themselves; that they were self-contained mini-narratives. A story can exist within a story. But a dream within a story is narrative gibberish.

And yet dreams still proliferate in pop culture. On a recent episode of Transparent, the popular TV series on Amazon, a character went to the dentist, and the ensuing nitrous-induced dream sequence had me checking football scores on my phone. After all, I’m no saint. I will not listen to your dreams.

Alex Tzelnic is a writer and teacher living in Cambridge, MA. He has resolved to tweet more in 2017, and you can follow his progress @atz840.

Facebooktwitterredditpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Filed Under: Misc. Philosophical Musings Tagged With: dreaming, dreams, fiction, philosophical blog

Comments

  1. Luke T says

    January 5, 2017 at 4:26 pm

    Great piece; well done!

    Reply
  2. Christopher Frederick says

    January 7, 2017 at 2:12 am

    I think the ‘problem’ of retelling dreams in life, or their use in fiction, is one of content and execution more than anything else…

    Reply
  3. Greg says

    January 8, 2017 at 3:30 am

    Near the beginning, you say there’s something “offensive” about listening to someone elses dreams, but completely ignore how offensive it is to have an acquaintance who thinks they’re entitled to your time by right, and will make obnoxious sounds with a buzzer until you capitulate. Like a little child pulling your pant leg and repeating your parentage title, until you respond. If I had a friend with such a buzzer, he wouldn’t be a friend for long.

    Reply
  4. Michael Murray says

    January 8, 2017 at 10:34 pm

    I think with proper attention to the dream tellers details both parties can discover something quite interesting. Usually if I’m trapped in a situation of someone retelling their dream to me I attempt to engage them and see whether or not they are willing to elaborate on the symbolic expressions which their mind conjured. If the individual is reluctant to discuss it is clear that no progress will be made and they fall into the category of those who are reassured by the apparent orderliness of the world that is spoken of.

    I am of the mind that the very notable mechanism of dreaming does not , as you seem to suggest , necessarily cause unhappiness to the dreamer or to whom they might retell the events to. Furthermore it doesn’t seem that dreams are full of chaos and irrationality. In my experience it has been a critical component to self-understanding and realization, one which constantly reaffirms the feeling of wonder and cheerful ignorance I have about human beings mental capability.

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

PEL Live Show 2023

Brothers K Live Show

Citizenship has its Benefits

Become a PEL Citizen
Become a PEL Citizen, and get access to all paywalled episodes, early and ad-free, including exclusive Part 2's for episodes starting September 2020; our after-show Nightcap, where the guys respond to listener email and chat more causally; a community of fellow learners, and more.

Rate and Review

Nightcap

Listen to Nightcap
On Nightcap, listen to the guys respond to listener email and chat more casually about their lives, the making of the show, current events and politics, and anything else that happens to come up.

Subscribe to Email Updates

Select list(s):

Check your inbox or spam folder to confirm your subscription.

Support PEL

Buy stuff through Amazon and send a few shekels our way at no extra cost to you.

Tweets by PartiallyExLife

Recent Comments

  • Seth Paskin on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • John Heath on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • Randy Strader on Ep. 309: Wittgenstein On Certainty (Part Two)
  • Wes Alwan on PEL Nightcap February 2023
  • Kunal on Why Don’t We Like Idealism?

About The Partially Examined Life

The Partially Examined Life is a philosophy podcast by some guys who were at one point set on doing philosophy for a living but then thought better of it. Each episode, we pick a text and chat about it with some balance between insight and flippancy. You don’t have to know any philosophy, or even to have read the text we’re talking about to (mostly) follow and (hopefully) enjoy the discussion

Become a PEL Citizen!

As a PEL Citizen, you’ll have access to a private social community of philosophers, thinkers, and other partial examiners where you can join or initiate discussion groups dedicated to particular readings, participate in lively forums, arrange online meet-ups for impromptu seminars, and more. PEL Citizens also have free access to podcast transcripts, guided readings, episode guides, PEL music, and other citizen-exclusive material. Click here to join.

Blog Post Categories

  • (sub)Text
  • Aftershow
  • Announcements
  • Audiobook
  • Book Excerpts
  • Citizen Content
  • Citizen Document
  • Citizen News
  • Close Reading
  • Combat and Classics
  • Constellary Tales
  • Exclude from Newsletter
  • Featured Ad-Free
  • Featured Article
  • General Announcements
  • Interview
  • Letter to the Editor
  • Misc. Philosophical Musings
  • Nakedly Examined Music Podcast
  • Nakedly Self-Examined Music
  • NEM Bonus
  • Not School Recording
  • Not School Report
  • Other (i.e. Lesser) Podcasts
  • PEL Music
  • PEL Nightcap
  • PEL's Notes
  • Personal Philosophies
  • Phi Fic Podcast
  • Philosophy vs. Improv
  • Podcast Episode (Citizen)
  • Podcast Episodes
  • Pretty Much Pop
  • Reviewage
  • Song Self-Exam
  • Supporter Exclusive
  • Things to Watch
  • Vintage Episode (Citizen)
  • Web Detritus

Follow:

Twitter | Facebook | Google+ | Apple Podcasts

Copyright © 2009 - 2023 · The Partially Examined Life, LLC. All rights reserved. Privacy Policy · Terms of Use · Copyright Policy

Copyright © 2023 · Magazine Pro Theme on Genesis Framework · WordPress · Log in