• Log In

The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast

A Philosophy Podcast and Philosophy Blog

Subscribe on Android Spotify Google Podcasts audible patreon
  • Home
  • Podcast
    • PEL Network Episodes
    • Publicly Available PEL Episodes
    • Paywalled and Ad-Free Episodes
    • PEL Episodes by Topic
    • Nightcap
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Pretty Much Pop
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • (sub)Text
    • Phi Fic Podcast
    • Combat & Classics
    • Constellary Tales
  • Blog
  • About
    • PEL FAQ
    • Meet PEL
    • About Pretty Much Pop
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • Meet Phi Fic
    • Listener Feedback
    • Links
  • Join
    • Become a Citizen
    • Join Our Mailing List
    • Log In
  • Donate
  • Store
    • Episodes
    • Swag
    • Everything Else
    • Cart
    • Checkout
    • My Account
  • Contact
  • Mailing List

Kitsch and Camp in the Age of Trump

February 21, 2018 by Rufus Hickok 1 Comment

Image by Bin im Garten

In this strange era, in which the dominant intellectual pastime has become analyzing the moods and behaviors of the American President (not so different, one imagines, from life at Versailles in the mid-eighteenth century) an interesting question about Donald Trump seems, to me at least, to be whether his style is more Kitsch or Camp?

I realize this concern puts me in company with the last few remaining dandies and practically no one else, yet the question still bedevils me and feels like the Rosetta Stone to understanding his entire presidency, and really an entire sort of political rule. Because kitsch famously gravitates toward authoritarianism or, more accurately, authoritarianism gravitates towards kitsch. Even toward totalitarianism; it is as easy, for instance, to recognize “Soviet Kitsch” as it is to spot “Fascist Kitsch,” although the two are often indistinguishable from one another. But, aside from the fever dreams of certain fundamentalists, I would argue that there really has rarely been such a thing as “Totalitarian Camp” as of yet. Camp requires a certain self-awareness, or, conversely, a naive frivolousness, that quickly becomes toxic to true authoritarians and rubs against the grain of kitsch.

Kitsch, in a sense, generates counterfeit emotions via a bogus image of reality.

It is not particularly easy to distinguish between kitsch and camp, which are both usually taken to be genres of “bad art,” albeit particularly charming ones. As in most matters of taste, definitions tend to be inexact, which quickly frustrates the literal-minded. There’s more than a little truth, for instance, in art historian Alan Gowans’s complaint that kitsch is simply “art for art’s sake, which happens to be out of avant-garde fashion.” As for camp, the discussion begins and ends with Susan Sontag’s 1964 essay “Notes on Camp,” where she says precious little about the differences between the two, if there are any, aside from the note that “Many examples of Camp are things which from a ‘serious’ point of view are either bad art or kitsch. Not all though.” Sontag details a “camp sensibility,” which finds pleasure in certain kinds of exaggerated, artificial, frivolous, and theatricalized art and personas, but there are clear areas of overlap with an appreciation of kitsch, a type of stilted sentimental art. Jayne Mansfield’s mansion, for instance (as seen in the tour de force of filmic bad taste, The Wild, Wild World of Jayne Mansfield), was both extremely “kitschy” and a textbook example of Sontag’s “naïve camp.”

We can flirt with camp in a moment, but let’s start with kitsch since its coinage is a bit older, although not by much. The term was possibly devised by Munich art dealers in the 1870s who called certain works of gaudy, sentimental art “kitsch” after the German Kitschen: to smear, spread, smear together quickly, etc. Kitsch art is seen as rushed, cheap, trashy, frequently unfinished, and in some sense insincere by “serious” art experts. It’s a knock-off. The modernist writer Hermann Broch argued that kitsch is merely a “system of imitation… it can resemble the object of imitation in every detail… but the element of imitation is bound to show through,” adding that “Kitsch is the element of evil in the system of art.” Kitsch, in a sense, generates counterfeit emotions via a bogus image of reality.

Broch ties its birth to Romanticism, “the mother of Kitsch.” Following (and in spite of) the Enlightenment, Romanticist art and literature seeks to illuminate the individual’s feelings of the absolute, divine, or cosmic and to elevate the everyday to the spiritual realm; yet at the same time, it recognizes that this task greatly exceeds man’s resources. There is thus a tragic element to Romanticism. In kitsch, the tragic element is removed and the art attempts to impose what Broch calls a “completely unreal condition on reality,” to turn life into a “neurotic work of art.” Broch sees this neurotic element as the root of Kitsch’s much-noted connection to Nazism.

Kitsch is easy. Walter Benjamin described kitsch as “unadulterated beauty” requiring no intellectual effort. Unsurprisingly, therefore, kitsch was the art form of choice for most totalitarian propaganda. Milan Kundera, who knew well the Soviet Czech version, described kitsch as an aesthetic “in which shit is denied and everyone acts as though it does not exist.” Kundera posits this as the aesthetic ideal of all politicians and political movements. I wonder: are those of us in the janitorial corps, who labor at removing traces of shit from public lavatories, agents of repression or prophets of liberation? The kitsch aesthetic would also have an obvious appeal to an avowed germophobe like Donald Trump, both politically and psychologically.

What can terms like “kitsch” and “camp” possibly mean in an era in which the style and mannerisms of the leader of the free world are so exaggerated as to lie beyond parody?

It also makes sense that kitsch became an issue of philosophical importance in the twentieth century, particularly by the time of the Second World War. In a famous 1939 essay, Clement Greenberg argued that the connection between kitsch and totalitarianism was simple opportunism. Greenberg considers kitsch “ersatz culture” and “the epitome of all that is spurious in our time.” A product of the Industrial Revolution, kitsch appeals to the masses primarily because it requires little time or effort to appreciate, unlike avant-garde art, and their working lives offer little room for either. Think of the mass popularity of Margaret Keane or Thomas Kinkade paintings. Since kitsch was “the culture of the masses” in Russia and Germany, promoting it was simply another of the “inexpensive ways in which totalitarian regimes seek to ingratiate themselves with their subjects.” His argument recalls Kundera but eludes the extent to which kitsch is a comprehensive aesthetic view of the world having deep ideological affinities with totalitarian ideology. Walter Benjamin’s description of kitsch as an “invitation to wallow in sentiment” could also apply to many, fairly potent modern political movements.

The camp aesthetic, by contrast, requires a certain amount of time and effort to learn to appreciate. Its patronage is not associated with a particular class, but from the time of its earliest coinage around the turn of the twentieth century, camp has been associated with homosexual males. Camp is an aesthetic that purposefully blends high and low culture, celebrating art and performances that are over-the-top, exaggerated, ostentatiously and superficially glamorous, highly artificial, and often dripping in excess. Sontag calls camp “the sensibility of failed seriousness, of the theatricalization of experience.” While one common distinction holds that kitsch is a style of art and camp a style of performance, Sontag notes that a style of plastic art can also be camp, particularly “decorative art emphasizing texture, sensuous surface, and style at the expense of content.” Certainly, the same qualities exist in camp fashion.

In fact, the modernist architect, critical writer (and large influence on Wittgenstein) Adolf Loos’s critical description of “good taste” in Vienna circa 1890 comes to mind here.

A craze for totally meaningless articles of decoration… a craze for satin-like surfaces: for silk satin and shining leather… as also for totally meaningless articles of decoration… Everything was mixed too, without rhyme or reason… there was a conspicuous absence of usefulness or purpose; it was all purely for show.

This is also what comes to mind when looking at the highly publicized pictures of Donald Trump’s gold- and marble-filled penthouse (which also strangely evoke thoughts of teeth).

Indeed, the entire Trump project, from the high-rise buildings to the ill-fated casinos to the Presidency, seems an exercise in grandiose self-expression worthy of Ozymandias. His persona is completely theatricalized and artificial. Strangely, one defense of Trump’s regular outbursts is identical to a frequent criticism: He doesn’t really mean what he says. There is an element of play to his pronouncements, of the flimflam man. Sontag’s “sensibility of failed seriousness” also comes to mind. Yet, what can terms like “kitsch” and “camp” possibly mean in an era in which the style and mannerisms of the leader of the free world are so exaggerated as to lie beyond parody?

To answer this, I would like to offer my own definitions of simple sentimental art, camp, and kitsch, and attempt to delineate what distinguishes the three categories. The usual caveats apply: these are inexact definitions drawing from my own subjective tastes and I am certainly neither a philosopher of aesthetics nor an art critic. However, I see the terms as fairly straightforward statements about how the person using them responds to a particular work of art.

  • Sentimental Art is that which aims at a noncognitive emotional response independent of reasoning on the part of the viewer. To borrow from the important 2005 work by Jennifer Robinson, it is art that evokes responses “deeper than reason.” This alone does not make it kitsch.
  • Many works of Sentimental Art evoke an emotional response by appealing to large and abstract categories with deep emotional resonance such as Romantic Love, Motherhood, the Fatherland, Friendship, and Home. This explains why most political art tends to be sentimental; it communicates directly with the greatest number of people. It is hard to persuade the masses with an intellectual case against “Family,” for instance.
  • “Kitsch” is the term we use for art that attempts to evoke this sort of noncognitive emotional response and falls short in some way; it is failed Sentimental Art that leaves us cold. It misses the mark. The effect is something like receiving an extravagant Valentine’s Day gift from someone to whom we’re not particularly attracted; it’s uncomfortable and seems somewhat insincere, as if the artist is trying too hard. We use the word “kitsch” to describe both that failure and our lack of response that identifies the failure.
  • With time and distance, most Sentimental Art becomes Kitsch, but not all. Nevertheless, all Kitsch begins as failed Sentimental Art.
  • Camp, in contrast, is creative expression that exaggerates the individual in a grandiose way. If it makes an appeal to larger values, it does so only in passing and only for that purpose. If, as Kundera says, kitsch says “How nice to be moved, together with all mankind!,” then camp says “How nice to be loving this man or woman, together with all the world!” It overlaps with kitsch in that camp makes an exaggerated emotional appeal and falls short. We call it camp because it also leaves us cold. However, it’s more a sort of exaggerated self-expression, even in the case of home décor. I would suggest that camp arises primarily with the bourgeois middle class for this reason. Personal expression becomes the work of a life.

As a personality cult, it is impossible to imagine the “movement” surviving past the Trump presidency, although there might well be lasting changes made to the American political structure behind the scenes.

And so, I think it’s fairly safe to say that the Trump persona and aesthetic style is thoroughly camp. The emphasis is forever on this exaggerated, theatricalized selfhood, instead of drawing deeply from any particular abstract or sentimentalized visions of the world. We could hardly imagine a Trumpian version of Ronald Reagan’s kitschy “Morning in America” spots. Even a phrase like “Make America Great Again” seems to point more toward the idea of a political slogan than any vision of the nation. The driving spirit of Trumpism is the projected grandeur, strength, hugeness, and even radiance of the individual Donald Trump. As a personality cult, it is impossible to imagine the “movement” surviving past the Trump presidency, although there might well be lasting changes made to the American political structure behind the scenes.

The advertising guru Elmer Wheeler famously advised that merchants “Sell the sizzle, not the steak.” This could easily be applied to many political leaders in an era in which the spectacle has come to replace any political center of gravity (see also: Justin Trudeau). In fact, what is happening now in the United States is the expected state of affairs in a société du spectacle in which the entertainment media considers itself to be kingmakers (or queenmakers). While much is made of Donald Trump’s behavior and mental state, it’s possible that these concerns will not turn out to be a real issue. Instead, the larger threat to the future of this society could be a citizenry that no longer wants to do the hard work of political organizing when they are not being dazzled by flickering images and theatrical displays.

Rufus F. Hickok is a freelance writer, cook, janitor, doctor of history, part-time editor, and singer in a punk rock band. Born in Virginia, he currently resides in Canada.

Facebooktwitterredditpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Filed Under: Featured Article, Misc. Philosophical Musings Tagged With: donald trump, kitsch, media critique, philosophy blog, politics and art

Comments

  1. Dan says

    February 28, 2018 at 3:47 pm

    I personally think of camp as being almost a distinctively gay style, so it’s strange to see Trump’s style described that way, though I think the label applies to some extent. If I’m understanding your point, you’re saying that kitsch typically stands for something (Homeland or whatever), whereas camp tends to stand only for itself (“look at me, ain’t I great”). As you put it, “Camp, in contrast, is creative expression that exaggerates the individual in a grandiose way.”

    That’s kind of true, though I think camp is more commonly used to alienate the viewer from his sense that moral norms are really pressing obligations that must be followed — which is I guess why both massive media corporations and oppressed minorities have found the style so useful. We can agree that the 60s Batman TV show is camp, right? If so, note that the Batman TV show doesn’t serve to express the awesomeness of an individual. It does, however, tend to put the viewer in a devil-may-care mood that, viewed cynically, was probably designed to persuade people that it was ok to watch trash TV for hours on end. We can call that a bad use of camp, since people really shouldn’t waste a ton of time watching TV, But obviously camp has its good uses as well when used as a way of trying to relieve the sense that one must follow bad norms (like the prohibition of homosexuality).

    I think that camp’s actual usefulness to Trump lies in the fact that all his ideas, to the extent he has them, boil down to the notion of “screw it let’s just break norms and be selfish.” So in business, he breaks commercial norms; with regards to relationships, he breaks norms of fidelity; and in politics, he breaks the implicit but fundamental norm that politics is aimed at some sort of collective good beyond the good of one man and his political base. Camp tends to flirt with selfishness, but usually as a sort of self-undermining joke (e.g., drag queens); Trump, in contrast, seems to propose selfishness as an ideology, and to get people to accept such an awful premise, he needs something that makes it feel like the moral norm against selfishness isn’t really so weighty — hence the reason he finds camp so useful.

    In any event, that’s my reading. Feel free to disagree.

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

PEL Live Show 2023

Brothers K Live Show

Citizenship has its Benefits

Become a PEL Citizen
Become a PEL Citizen, and get access to all paywalled episodes, early and ad-free, including exclusive Part 2's for episodes starting September 2020; our after-show Nightcap, where the guys respond to listener email and chat more causally; a community of fellow learners, and more.

Rate and Review

Nightcap

Listen to Nightcap
On Nightcap, listen to the guys respond to listener email and chat more casually about their lives, the making of the show, current events and politics, and anything else that happens to come up.

Subscribe to Email Updates

Select list(s):

Check your inbox or spam folder to confirm your subscription.

Support PEL

Buy stuff through Amazon and send a few shekels our way at no extra cost to you.

Tweets by PartiallyExLife

Recent Comments

  • Theo on Ep. 308: Moore’s Proof of Mind-Independent Reality (Part Two)
  • Seth Paskin on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • John Heath on PEL Eulogies Nightcap Late March 2023
  • Randy Strader on Ep. 309: Wittgenstein On Certainty (Part Two)
  • Wes Alwan on PEL Nightcap February 2023

About The Partially Examined Life

The Partially Examined Life is a philosophy podcast by some guys who were at one point set on doing philosophy for a living but then thought better of it. Each episode, we pick a text and chat about it with some balance between insight and flippancy. You don’t have to know any philosophy, or even to have read the text we’re talking about to (mostly) follow and (hopefully) enjoy the discussion

Become a PEL Citizen!

As a PEL Citizen, you’ll have access to a private social community of philosophers, thinkers, and other partial examiners where you can join or initiate discussion groups dedicated to particular readings, participate in lively forums, arrange online meet-ups for impromptu seminars, and more. PEL Citizens also have free access to podcast transcripts, guided readings, episode guides, PEL music, and other citizen-exclusive material. Click here to join.

Blog Post Categories

  • (sub)Text
  • Aftershow
  • Announcements
  • Audiobook
  • Book Excerpts
  • Citizen Content
  • Citizen Document
  • Citizen News
  • Close Reading
  • Combat and Classics
  • Constellary Tales
  • Exclude from Newsletter
  • Featured Ad-Free
  • Featured Article
  • General Announcements
  • Interview
  • Letter to the Editor
  • Misc. Philosophical Musings
  • Nakedly Examined Music Podcast
  • Nakedly Self-Examined Music
  • NEM Bonus
  • Not School Recording
  • Not School Report
  • Other (i.e. Lesser) Podcasts
  • PEL Music
  • PEL Nightcap
  • PEL's Notes
  • Personal Philosophies
  • Phi Fic Podcast
  • Philosophy vs. Improv
  • Podcast Episode (Citizen)
  • Podcast Episodes
  • Pretty Much Pop
  • Reviewage
  • Song Self-Exam
  • Supporter Exclusive
  • Things to Watch
  • Vintage Episode (Citizen)
  • Web Detritus

Follow:

Twitter | Facebook | Google+ | Apple Podcasts

Copyright © 2009 - 2023 · The Partially Examined Life, LLC. All rights reserved. Privacy Policy · Terms of Use · Copyright Policy

Copyright © 2023 · Magazine Pro Theme on Genesis Framework · WordPress · Log in