• Log In

The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast

A Philosophy Podcast and Philosophy Blog

Subscribe on Android Spotify Google Podcasts audible patreon
  • Home
  • Podcast
    • PEL Network Episodes
    • Publicly Available PEL Episodes
    • Paywalled and Ad-Free Episodes
    • PEL Episodes by Topic
    • Nightcap
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Pretty Much Pop
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • (sub)Text
    • Phi Fic Podcast
    • Combat & Classics
    • Constellary Tales
  • Blog
  • About
    • PEL FAQ
    • Meet PEL
    • About Pretty Much Pop
    • Philosophy vs. Improv
    • Nakedly Examined Music
    • Meet Phi Fic
    • Listener Feedback
    • Links
  • Join
    • Become a Citizen
    • Join Our Mailing List
    • Log In
  • Donate
  • Store
    • Episodes
    • Swag
    • Everything Else
    • Cart
    • Checkout
    • My Account
  • Contact
  • Mailing List

There Is More to Seeing Than Meets the Eye: Rejecting Scruton’s Conception of Photography

May 31, 2018 by Tony Cearns 5 Comments

Photographers of a thoughtful demeanor should take a keen interest in what we mean by “seeing.” Are there different types of seeing? Does each visual art have a particular mode of seeing? Is there a difference between “looking” and “seeing”? To what extent is seeing different than thinking?

The English philosopher Roger Scruton attempted to answer these questions in one of the foundational texts in philosophical aesthetics, “Photography and Representation” (Critical Inquiry 7:3; Spring 1981). Scruton argued that photographs cannot be artworks because, unlike paintings, they cannot “represent,” that is, they cannot “sensuously embody … idea(s)” in ways that give rise to aesthetic satisfaction. Put more simply, Scruton argued that a painter could inflect within a painting references to further thoughts, as for example one might see into Hopper's painting, Nighthawks, thoughts about loneliness and alienation. Scruton called this type of seeing, seeing as.

Figure 1. Nighthawks, 1942 by Edward Hopper; © The Art Institute of Chicago

A photograph however, Scruton continues, is tied to the visual scene it depicts. It cannot depict it in any other way than that state of affairs presented to the lens. The photographer can only “capture” the objects within a frame as they appear but cannot inflect into the photograph references to further thoughts without departing from the photographic process and using non-photographic (“painterly”) techniques, such as burning, dodging, altering contrast, and so on. In short, photographs cannot be “fictive.”

An obvious way to counter Scruton would be to argue that his conception of the photographic process is too narrow to encapsulate what photographers actually do. Defining the photographic process solely in terms of the photo-chemical or electronic process instigated by a shutter-release leaves out those bits of photography that give expression to a photographer's visualization of a scene. Many philosophers have used variants of this type of argument. Some, however, have argued that it is this very narrow process that makes photography so distinctive from other artistic enterprises. The causal link between photographs and the scenes that they depict gives photography its characteristic charm.

But is there not something more fundamental at stake here than mere quibbling about what we mean by photography or art? Scruton cleaves a sharp divide between seeing as and merely seeing. This sharp distinction puts him in an untenable philosophical position: that seeing is inert, incapable of sequestering thoughts by virtue of what is being seen.

But what if seeing as and seeing were but two parts of the same process—say, picturing, to give it a different name with a wider connotation? In that case, seeing would not be inert; it would simply be the start of a process called picturing. Its phenomenal (i.e., nonconceptual) aspects would guide the mode of understanding by which we judge things to visually be what they are: objects, say. Picturing would involve a seeing with bare recognition and as we look more closely, the phenomenal content would provide further structures for conceptual shapings by which perceptions come into a process of thought. For Scruton, seeing is causal, that is, merely mechanical. But is it so unreasonable to suppose that seeing is more than this, and indeed not exhausted by conceptual understanding but rather invoking a surplus of sense beyond this, as argued Sellars? 

For Wilfrid Sellars, seeing has a nonpropositional component that provides the phenomenal content that underpins the process of picturing. Seeing a pink ice-cube, say, is different than thinking a pink ice-cube. In the words of Sellars:

… there is all the difference in the world between seeing something to be a pink ice-cube and merely thinking something to be a pink ice-cube ... over and above its propositional character … [perceptual] thinking has an additional character by virtue of which it is a seeing as contrasted with a mere thinking.1 

The pinkness of the ice-cube has an immediacy and presence that is different than the way it is in thought. If we subtract from seeing pinkness the thought of pinkness, we are left with a remainder that is the phenomenal content of seeing. The conceptual apprehension of pinkness underdetermines what it is. This phenomenal content is nonconceptual and therefore not available to scrutiny through thinking (for to do so would be to conceptualize it). We can only intuit it as the result of transcendentally framing an inquiry into the conditions that must pertain for us to have this immediate experience of pinkness that fades when we leave its presence, for its half-life is measured in seconds.

The distinction between seeing as and seeing finally comes into focus. The contents present in seeing as and seeing are well accounted for as conceptual content. Seeing the cube as ice is very like seeing it while believing in its iciness. In this regard, seeing is like thinking. Some of the visual content in seeing is present in the mode of being thought. However, there is also an essential difference since not everything in a visual experience is present in this way: “We see no only that the cube is pink, and see it as pink, we see the very pinkness of the object…”2 

The mode of understanding that arises from seeing is partly articulated through bodily dispositions that stem from navigating a picture through its perceptual forms. As Kant recognised, what is apprehended when we picture something is not just a perceptual shape, but a purposiveness “… (the) transcendental principle which represents a purposiveness in nature … in the form of a thing.”3

Contra Scruton, a photograph therefore can be seen in terms of an expression of a thought. If we make dubious distinctions between types of seeing— one for painting and one for photography—we get into a muddle. If we look more deeply into this muddle, we see that it comes from a curious habit that many philosophers have of limiting our understanding of things to cognitive understanding, that is, an understanding that involves only propositional content. It seems to me that to restrict aesthetic pleasure only to cognitive understanding is to miss the essence of what a pleasurable thing is. It is to Sellars’s credit that he recognized that there is more to seeing than meets the eye and that the ensuing surplus is phenomenal. It is a shame, however, that he did not question the whole idea of mental representation, but that’s another story.  


[1] Castaneda Calderon, Héctor Neri, and Wilfrid Sellars. (1975). Action, Knowledge, and Reality: Critical Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

[2] Sellars, Wilfrid. 1982. “Sensa or Sensings: Reflections on the Ontology of Perception,” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition: 83.

[3] Kant, Immanuel. 1790. Critique of Judgement: 36.


Tony Cearns is a photographer and tenkara angler based in Liverpool, England, who is researching the notion of affordance and mood in aesthetics and health. He is not affiliated to or employed by any institution. 


 

Facebooktwitterredditpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Filed Under: Featured Article, Misc. Philosophical Musings Tagged With: aesthetics, art critique, philosophy blog, Roger Scruton, Wilfrid Sellars

Comments

  1. Frédérique Gerbaud says

    May 31, 2018 at 4:43 pm

    Hello Tony,

    This is a very good article, thank you.
    I have a question with regards to “the notion of affordance and mood”. What do you mean?
    Hope you are well.
    Plus de nouvelles bientôt!
    Frédérique

    Reply
  2. Tony Cearns says

    June 1, 2018 at 12:24 pm

    Hi Frédérique.

    Thank you for your kind comment.

    Affordance – JJ Gibson proposed that we perceive possibilities for action (affordances) which are given by the environment. The environment ‘pulls’ actions out of you, as it were. A common example is that a chair affords sitting for a person of the right size, but not for a baby, say. The notion is getting quite a bit of attention, recently by Andy Clark’s Surfing Uncertainty [(2016)], Ruth Millikan’s Beyond Concepts [(2017)] and Daniel Dennett’s From Bacteria to Bach and Back [(2017)].

    In visual perception I think there is some mileage to be had from thinking about gestalt forms as a hierarchy of affordances

    Mood: ’Mood’ plays an important role in Heidegger’s “Being and Time’. Reading Blattner’s interpretation of Being and Time, Mood discloses the way things matter to us; Moods are atmospheric, that is we are steeped in them rather than they being private interior states; Moods reveal to us how we are faring.

    Best regards,
    Tony

    Reply
  3. Avi says

    June 23, 2018 at 1:30 pm

    It seems like your argument turns on your opinion of the thought/feeling binary, which I would be interested in hearing more about.

    Scruton, seems to be claiming that photographs cannot represent anything, which is remarkable, because “a photograph of Venice” is NOT Venice, and is merely a 2D section of colored space, except to the extent that we see it as representing (fictitiously) the literal Venice. Not having actually read Scruton’s argument I can’t see how it is interpretable as anything but elitism in favor of his preferred artistic mode.

    What is Art, though? It seems like your piece counters Scruton, and claims that photographs can be art to the extent that they can “be seen in terms of an expression of a thought.” It appears then that you agree with me that any sensory experience could be the basis of art, but the interesting question to me is how you distinguish between sensory content that is and is not art, given all the means by which we imbue physical structures that convey sensory content with expressions of thought. How do you distinguish art from communication? When I say “It is raining outside,” am I not imbuing sensory content (sounds) in physical structures (vibrating air) with expressions in thought (it is raining outside)? What if I throw a rock at someone from a roof only to see how they will react? Does the thought-content involve “there is a rock hitting you?” Is that not art because all I “send” to them is a chunk of sensory input? But isn’t that chunk necessarily involved with thought, because one always thinks about one’s feelings – at least to some extent? What if I just yell gibberish at someone? Is that performance art? Is the thoughtful content “look at me?” If I place a piece of art in a cave, never to be seen again, is it art? Does it need an audience?

    A phrase I have heard before that I like is “being the artist of your own experience.” To me that just sounds like thinking – imposing thoughtful content and conceptual structure on sensory content. The only difference being that the recipient of that thoughtful content is only myself, and the sensory content is not necessarily being “molded” or “casted” or “reshaped,” I am just looking at it, or “seeing it as.”

    I think your argument implicitly rests on the system you take as given that gives meaning to thought and feeling, and art itself. I would be curious to hear how you answer these kinds of questions.

    Avi

    Reply
  4. Tony Cearns says

    June 25, 2018 at 1:55 am

    Hi Avi
    I think Scruton’s argument is more sophisticated but your conclusion is correct.

    I would assert as follows:

    1. All experience (whether aesthetic or otherwise) is the correlation between a subjective consciousness and the structure of objects presenting themselves. Subject and Object are tied to each other in such a way as to make meaningless any attempt to assert a separate existence to ‘Mind’ or ‘Object’ in terms of experience.

    2, Similarly, ‘Thinking’ and “Seeing” (or any other sensory feeling) are not independent of each other. When I see something I also have a sense of touching it, for example. Seeing has a haptic quality. I’m not sure what you mean by ‘binary’, but I would say that Thinking and Seeing are interdependent. Seeing and Thinking co-develop in an episode of “Seeing as’. Scruton has Seeing as independent to Thinking.

    3: Experience is given in an aesthetic form. Experience is the crystallisation of an aesthetic form (aisthesis) as a concrete event. Aesthetic forms have a gestalt quality and a mode of articulation (affordance and possibility are useful concepts here with which to explore this)).

    4. Experience is articulated through language. Language is not only to be seen in terms of a Fregean subject/predicate, concept/object type or solely in referential terms, as in Semiotics. Language is lived as an aesthetic form and has gestalt qualities.

    5. Aesthetic forms convey meaning through the complex arrays and hierarchies of properties that constitute gestalt phenomena. Meaning has little to do with representation and more to do with positional information. Representation is subordinate to the primacy of aesthetic forms. Mereological principles underpin meaning-constituting aesthetic forms.

    6. Art is the articulation of Experience as part of a language game, reinforced through institutional norms.

    I realise I make huge leaps here….

    Thank you once again for your input.

    Reply
  5. Enver Hoxha says

    June 3, 2022 at 11:35 am

    Scruton is right. Photographs are linked causally to some other objects and are images of them. Paintings are not ‘images’, no matter what techniques are used.
    You are dead wrong.

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

PEL Live Show 2023

Brothers K Live Show

Citizenship has its Benefits

Become a PEL Citizen
Become a PEL Citizen, and get access to all paywalled episodes, early and ad-free, including exclusive Part 2's for episodes starting September 2020; our after-show Nightcap, where the guys respond to listener email and chat more causally; a community of fellow learners, and more.

Rate and Review

Nightcap

Listen to Nightcap
On Nightcap, listen to the guys respond to listener email and chat more casually about their lives, the making of the show, current events and politics, and anything else that happens to come up.

Subscribe to Email Updates

Select list(s):

Check your inbox or spam folder to confirm your subscription.

Support PEL

Buy stuff through Amazon and send a few shekels our way at no extra cost to you.

Tweets by PartiallyExLife

Recent Comments

  • Randy Strader on Ep. 309: Wittgenstein On Certainty (Part Two)
  • Wes Alwan on PEL Nightcap February 2023
  • Kunal on Why Don’t We Like Idealism?
  • Ronald Cogen on Ep. 311: Understanding the Dao De Jing (Part One)
  • Brian Grindel on PEL Nightcap February 2023

About The Partially Examined Life

The Partially Examined Life is a philosophy podcast by some guys who were at one point set on doing philosophy for a living but then thought better of it. Each episode, we pick a text and chat about it with some balance between insight and flippancy. You don’t have to know any philosophy, or even to have read the text we’re talking about to (mostly) follow and (hopefully) enjoy the discussion

Become a PEL Citizen!

As a PEL Citizen, you’ll have access to a private social community of philosophers, thinkers, and other partial examiners where you can join or initiate discussion groups dedicated to particular readings, participate in lively forums, arrange online meet-ups for impromptu seminars, and more. PEL Citizens also have free access to podcast transcripts, guided readings, episode guides, PEL music, and other citizen-exclusive material. Click here to join.

Blog Post Categories

  • (sub)Text
  • Aftershow
  • Announcements
  • Audiobook
  • Book Excerpts
  • Citizen Content
  • Citizen Document
  • Citizen News
  • Close Reading
  • Combat and Classics
  • Constellary Tales
  • Exclude from Newsletter
  • Featured Ad-Free
  • Featured Article
  • General Announcements
  • Interview
  • Letter to the Editor
  • Misc. Philosophical Musings
  • Nakedly Examined Music Podcast
  • Nakedly Self-Examined Music
  • NEM Bonus
  • Not School Recording
  • Not School Report
  • Other (i.e. Lesser) Podcasts
  • PEL Music
  • PEL Nightcap
  • PEL's Notes
  • Personal Philosophies
  • Phi Fic Podcast
  • Philosophy vs. Improv
  • Podcast Episode (Citizen)
  • Podcast Episodes
  • Pretty Much Pop
  • Reviewage
  • Song Self-Exam
  • Supporter Exclusive
  • Things to Watch
  • Vintage Episode (Citizen)
  • Web Detritus

Follow:

Twitter | Facebook | Google+ | Apple Podcasts

Copyright © 2009 - 2023 · The Partially Examined Life, LLC. All rights reserved. Privacy Policy · Terms of Use · Copyright Policy

Copyright © 2023 · Magazine Pro Theme on Genesis Framework · WordPress · Log in